An experiment in mathematical exposition.
Many people feel attracted to the implication on account of the simplicity of the associated inference rules
A ⇒ B (1) B ⇒ C ----------- A ⇒ C A ⇒ B (2) C ⇒ D ----------- A ∧ C ⇒ B ∧ D A ⇒ B (3) C ⇒ D ----------- A ∨ C ⇒ B ∨ DThe transitivity of (1), and the symmetry of (2) and of (3) are clearly appealing. Rule (1), however, is a direct consequence of, and rules (2) and (3) are merely two different transcriptions of the same
A ∨ B (4) C ∨ D ------------- A ∨ C ∨ (B ∧ D) ,a rule, which --on account of the symmetry of the disjunction-- can be applied in four different ways to the two given antecedents. Rules (2) and (3) give only two of the four. Rule (1) emerges as the special case
A ∨ B C ∨ ¬B ------------- A ∨ C .
I called this "a direct consequence" because --perhaps somewhat arbitrarily-- I would like to distinguish between inference rules (different applications of which may yield results that are not equivalent) and simplifications that are possible according to boolean algebra --such as replacing B ∧ ¬B by false and A ∨ C ∨ false by A ∨ C-- , but never change the value of the boolean expression.
* | * | |
* |
The above caused me to revisit the problem of the nine mathematicians visiting an international congress, and about whom we are invited to prove
A ∨ B ∨ C (5)
with
A: | there exists a triple of mathematicians that is incommunicado (i.e. such that no two of them have a language in common) |
B: | there exists a mathematician mastering more than three languages |
C: | there exists a language mastered by at least three mathematicians. |
Very much like the introduction of (named!) auxiliary lines or points in geometry proofs, I propose to introduce named auxiliary propositions, such that
we can prove lemmata connecting them to the above propositions, such as
D: | there exists a mathematician that can communicate with more others than he masters languages, |
C ∨ | "each mathematician communicates in different languages with those others he can communicate with", etc. |
as with observing | |
¬D ∨ | "there exists a mathematician that shares a language with at least two others", etc. |
With
E: | there exists a mathematician that can communicate with more than three others, |
G: | for each x, the equation x | u has at least five different solutions for u, |
E ∨ G (6)
With
H: | with y and z constrained to belong to an arbitrary quintuple, the equation y|z has at least one solution in y and z, |
E ∨ H . (7)Applying rule (4) to assertions (6) and (7) we find E ∨ (G ∧ H) ,
E ∨ | "for each x, the equation x | y ∧ x | z ∧ y | z has at least one solution in y and z". |
Applying rule (4) to Lemmata 1 and 2 we infer the
Corollary. A ∨ C ∨ (E ∧ ¬D) .
Remembering rule (4) we see that (5) has been proved when we can prove B ∨ ¬(E ∧ ¬D)
or, equivalently
Lemma 3. B ∨ D ∨ ¬E.
Proof. Obvious. (End of proof of Lemma 3).
* | * | |
* |
Note that in the above the Corollary was only used for heuristic purposes. Once Lemmata 1, 2, and 3 have been established we could have inferred
A ∨ E B ∨ D ∨ ¬E --------------- A ∨ B ∨ D | and |
A ∨ B ∨ D C ∨ ¬D --------------- A ∨ B ∨ C |
and our two individual inferences would have been of the traditional form of the transitive implication.
* | * | |
* |
I know that firm believers in the so-called "natural deduction" will state that, in the case of Lemma 2, I am just "deducing naturally" that A follows from the "assumption" ¬E. In this appreciation they will find themselves strengthened by the observation that in that proof all assertions start with "E ∨". They have a point, but the point is weak. Look at the structure of the proof as a whole. Lemmata 1, 2, and 3 capture it; from there rule (4) does the job, and at that level it is very arbitrary to subdivide assertions into assumptions and conclusions.
Remark. Observing the seven triples xyz for a pair (x,y) such that x | y , the argument proving Lemma 2 can equally well be phrased in terms of assertions starting with "A ∨". In the sense used above also Lemma 2 is obvious. (End of remark.)
Plataanstraat 5 5671 AL NUENEN The Netherlands |
27 February 1980 prof.dr. Edsger W. Dijkstra Burroughs Research Fellow |
Last revised on