The
〈∀x: x < n: hyp.x〉 ⇒ hyp.n
Notice in the above proof the absence of separate treatments of "base" and "step". (End of Remark.)
(Courtesy A. J. M. van Gasteren)
* *
*
The above has been written down so that we may compare it with how Mark Kac and Stanslaw M. Ulam treat the matter on the 1st page of Chapter 1 of their "Mathematics and Logic":
The following proof, probably still the simplest, asserts the mere existence of arbitrarily large primes. Suppose the number were finite; there would then be a largest prime p. Consider now the number n = p! + 1 (p! is read "p factorial" and equals 1 ∙ 2 ∙ 3 … p). This number is not divisible by any prime up to p. If there is no prime between p and n, as we have assumed, then n itself would be prime, contrary to our assumption that p is the largest one.
The authors hesitate between dealing with the number of primes and the value of primes: the first sentence deals with their values, the second one mentions their number. The conclusion of the second sentence is unwarranted: suppose there were no primes at all, then their number would have been finite (viz. zero), but there would not have been a largest prime p. (I would like the reader to appreciate that the argument in our proof of Lemma 1 is perfectly valid when S is empty.) The second sentence would have been better had they just written: "Suppose there were a largest prime p.".
The third sentence introduces n, the fourth sentence is the first one whose correctness depends on the concept "prime". Unfortunately, the authors opened their chapter a little earlier with:
So, 1 is included in their primes, and the conclusion in their fourth sentence is just wrong. [This is another illustration of the fact that including 1 among the prime numbers is an unfortunate interface.]1. The Infinity of Primes
Among the so-called natural numbers (1, 2, 3, and so on) are some that are divisible only by 1 and by themselves; these are called the prime numbers. The prime numbers are the building blocks of all the numbers in the sense that every natural number is the product of powers of the primes that divide it. For instance 60 = 22∙3∙5. The first several primes are 1, 2, 3, 5, 7, 11, 13, 17. It can be asked whether the series goes on forever, or, in other words, whether there is a largest prime. The answer is that there is no largest prime. This has been known since the golden age of Greece. It was proved by Euclid in the 3rd century B.C. His argument is as clear and fresh today as ever.
The fifth sentence is supposed to conclude the proof, but it is very elliptic as it does not mention which property of prime numbers should justify the conclusion. It looks as if we are invited to conclude from the fact that none of the numbers between p and n is prime that none of these numbers divides n, and I hope that we are not supposed to use that "Every natural number is the product of [positive] powers of the primes that divide it", for otherwise we could apply the possibility of that factorization to n directly and conclude, without the assumption that p was the largest prime, because n ≥ 2 the existence of a prime larger than p. The last step of the quoted proof needs a possibly unstated and in any case unproven lemma (whose proof almost certainly requires mathematical induction). What an awful mess! And that in a book with the title "Mathematics and Logic"!
Now we are at it, I draw the reader's attention to the following sentence from the second quotation:
However, the answer to the first question is "yes", and to the second one "no"."It can be asked whether the series [of primes] goes on forever, or, in other words, whether there is a largest prime."
Mark Kac and Stanislaw M. Ulam, "Mathematics and Logic", originally published: New York: Praeger, 1968, in series: Brittanica perspective. Dover Publications, Mineola, NY, 1992.
Austin, 17 March 1995