(MEMBER (FOO A) (APPEND (BAR B) (MUM C)))
Major Section: INTRODUCTION-TO-THE-THEOREM-PROVER
What rules come to mind when looking at the following subterm of a Key Checkpoint? Think of strong rules (see strong-rewrite-rules).
(MEMBER (FOO A) (APPEND (BAR B) (MUM C)))
Since (append x y)
contains all the members of x
and all the members
of y
, e
is a member of (append x y)
precisely when e
is a
member of x
or of y
. So a strong statement of this is:
(defthm member-append-strong-false (equal (member e (append x y)) (or (member e x) (member e y))))
However, this is not a theorem because member
is not Boolean.
(Member e x)
, for example, returns the first tail of x
that starts
with e
, or else nil
. To see an example of this formula that
evaluates to nil
, let
e = 3 x = '(1 2 3) y = '(4 5 6).Then the left-hand side,
(member e (append x y))
evaluates to (3 4 5 6)
while
the right-hand side evaluates to (3)
.However, the two sides are propositionally equivalent (both either nil
or non-nil
together). So this is a useful :rewrite
rule:
(defthm member-append-strong (iff (member e (append x y)) (or (member e x) (member e y)))).It tells the system that whenever it encounters an instance of
(MEMBER e (APPEND x y))
in a propositional occurrence (where only
its truthvalue is relevant), it should be replaced by this
disjunction of (MEMBER e x)
and (MEMBER e y)
.The following two formulas are true but provide much weaker rules and we would not add them:
(implies (member e x) (member e (append x y))) (implies (member e y) (member e (append x y)))because they each cause the system to backchain upon seeing
(MEMBER e (APPEND x y))
expressions and will not apply unless one of the two side-conditions can be established.There is a rewrite rule that is even stronger than member-append-strong
.
It is suggested by the counterexample, above, for the EQUAL
version of the rule.
(defthm member-append-really-strong (equal (member e (append x y)) (if (member e x) (append (member e x) y) (member e y))))While
member-append-strong
only rewrites member-append
expressions
occurring propositionally, the -really-strong
version rewrites every
occurrence.However, this rule will be more useful than member-append-strong
only
if you have occurrences of member
in non-propositional places. For example,
suppose you encountered a term like:
(CONS (MEMBER e (APPEND x y)) z).Then the
-strong
rule does not apply but the -really-strong
rule does.Furthermore, the -really-strong
rule, by itself, is not quite as good as
the -strong
rule in propositional settings! For example, if you have proved
the -really-strong
rule, you'll notice that the system still has to use
induction to prove
(IMPLIES (MEMBER E A) (MEMBER E (APPEND B A))).The
-really-strong
rule would rewrite it to
(IMPLIES (MEMBER E A) (IF (MEMBER E A) (APPEND (MEMBER E A) B) (MEMBER E B)))which would further simplify to
(IMPLIES (MEMBER E A) (APPEND (MEMBER E A) B))What lemma does this suggest? The answer is the rather odd:
(implies x (append x y))which rewrites propositional occurrences of
(APPEND x y)
to T
if
x
is non-nil
. This is an inductive fact about append
. A problem with the -really-strong
rule is that it transforms even
propositional occurrences of member
into mixed propositional and
non-propositional occurrences.
(defthm member-append-really-strong (equal (member e (append x y)) ; <-- even if this is a propositional occurrence (if (member e x) (append (member e x) y) ; <-- the member in here is not! (member e y))))So if you are using the
-really-strong
lemma in a situation in which
all your member
expressions are used propositionally, you'll suddenly
find yourself confronted with non-propositional uses of member
.Our advice is not to use the -really-strong
version unless your application is
inherently using member
in a non-propositional way.
Use your browser's Back Button now to return to practice-formulating-strong-rules.